Grothendieck universe
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia.
1.
If x ∈ U and if y ∈ x, then y ∈ U.
2.
If x,y ∈ U, then {x,y}
∈ U.
4.
If is a family of elements
of U,
and if I ∈U,
then the union is an element of U.
A Grothendieck universe
is meant to provide a set in which all of mathematics can be performed. (In
fact, it provides a model for set theory.) As an
example, we will prove an easy proposition.
Proposition 1.
If x ∈ U and y ⊆ x, then y ∈ U.
Proof.
y ∈ P(x) because y ⊆ x. P(x) ∈ U because x ∈ U, so y ∈ U.
It is similarly easy to
prove that any Grothendieck universe U contains:
- All singletons of each of its elements,
- All products of all families of
elements of U indexed by an element of U,
- All disjoint unions of all
families of elements of U indexed by an element of U,
- All intersections of all
families of elements of U indexed by an element of U,
- All functions between any two
elements of U, and
- All subsets of U whose cardinal is an element of U.
In particular, it
follows from the last axiom that if U is non-empty, it must
contain all of its finite subsets and a subset of each finite cardinality. One
can also prove immediately from the definitions that the intersection of any
class of universes is a universe.
Grothendieck universes
are equivalent to strongly inaccessible cardinals. More formally, the
following two axioms are equivalent:
(U) For all sets x, there exists a
Grothendieck universe U such that x ∈ U.
(C) For all cardinals κ, there is a strongly
inaccessible cardinal λ which is strictly larger than κ.
To prove this fact, we
give explicit constructions. Let κ be a strongly inaccessible cardinal. Say
that a set S is
strictly of type κ if for any sequence sn ∈ ... ∈ s0∈ S, |sn|
< κ. (S itself
corresponds to the empty sequence.) Then the set u(κ) of all sets strictly of
type κ is a Grothendieck universe of cardinality κ. The proof of this fact is
long, so for details, we refer to Bourbaki's article, listed in the references.
To show that the large
cardinal axiom (C) implies the universe axiom (U), choose a set x. Let x0 = x, and for all n, let xn = ∪x be the union of the
elements ofx. Let y = ∪nxn. By (C), there is a
strongly inaccessible cardinal κ such that |y| < κ. Let u(κ) be the universe of the
previous paragraph. x is
strictly of type κ, so x ∈ u(κ). To show that the
universe axiom (U) implies the large cardinal axiom (C), choose a strongly
inaccessible cardinal κ. κ is the cardinality of the Grothendieck universe u(κ). By (U), there is a
Grothendieck universe V such that U ∈ V. Then κ < 2κ ≤ |V|.
In fact, any
Grothendieck universe is of the form u(κ) for some κ. This gives
another form of the equivalence between Grothendieck universes and strongly
inaccessible cardinals:
For any Grothendieck universe U, |U| is a
strongly inaccessible cardinal, and for any strongly inaccessible cardinal κ,
there is a Grothendieck universe u(κ). Furthermore, u(|U|)=U, and
|u(κ)|=κ.
Since the existence of
strongly inaccessible cardinals cannot be proved from the axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel
set theory, the existence of universes cannot be proved from Zermelo-Fraenkel
set theory either.
The idea of universes is
due to Alexander
Grothendieck, who used them as a way of avoiding proper classes in algebraic
geometry.
Bourbaki, N., Univers, appendix to Exposé I
of Artin, M., Grothendieck, A., Verdier, J. L., eds., Théorie des Topos et
Cohomologie Étale des Schémas (SGA 4), second edition, Springer-Verlag, Heidelberg,
1972.
Views
Personal tools
Navigation
Search
Toolbox
- This page was last modified
14:45, 7 October 2005.
- All text is available under the
terms of the GNU Free Documentation License (see Copyrights for details).
- About Wikipedia
- Disclaimers
Grothendieck universe
From
Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
1.
If x is an element of U and if y is an element of x, then y is also an element of U. (U is a transitive set.)
2.
If x and y are both elements of U, then {x,y} is
an element of U.
4.
If is a family
of elements of U, and if I is an element of U, then the union is an
element of U.
Elements of a Grothendieck universe are sometimes called small sets.
A Grothendieck universe is
meant to provide a set in which all of mathematics can be performed. (In fact,
uncountable Grothendieck universes provide models of
set theory with the natural ∈-relation, natural powerset operation etc.) As an example, we will
prove an easy proposition.
Proposition.
If and ,
then .
Proof. because . because , so .
The axioms of Grothendieck
universes imply that every set is an element of some Grothendieck universe.
It is similarly easy to prove
that any Grothendieck universe U contains:
·
All products of all families of
elements of U indexed by an element of U,
·
All disjoint unions of all families
of elements of U indexed by an element of U,
·
All intersections of all families
of elements of U indexed by an element of U,
·
All functions between any two
elements of U, and
·
All subsets of U whose cardinal is an element of U.
In particular, it follows
from the last axiom that if U is non-empty, it must contain all of
its finite subsets and a subset of each finite cardinality. One can also prove
immediately from the definitions that the intersection of any class of
universes is a universe.
The idea of universes is due
to Alexander Grothendieck, who used
them as a way of avoiding proper classes in algebraic geometry.
Grothendieck universes and inaccessible cardinals[edit]
There are two simple examples
of Grothendieck universes:
·
The empty set, and
Other examples are more
difficult to construct. Loosely speaking, this is because Grothendieck
universes are equivalent tostrongly inaccessible cardinals.
More formally, the following two axioms are equivalent:
(U) For each
set x, there exists a
Grothendieck universe U such that x ∈ U.
(C) For each
cardinal κ, there is a strongly inaccessible cardinal λ that is strictly larger
than κ.
To prove this fact, we
introduce the function c(U).
Define:
where by |x| we mean
the cardinality of x. Then
for any universe U, c(U) is either zero or
strongly inaccessible. Assuming it is non-zero, it is a strong limit cardinal
because the power set of any element of U is an element of U and every element of U is a subset of U. To see that it is regular,
suppose that cλ is a collection of cardinals indexed
by I, where the
cardinality of I and of each cλ is less than c(U). Then, by the
definition of c(U), I and each cλ can be replaced by an element of U. The union of elements of Uindexed by an element of U is an element of U, so the sum of the cλ has the cardinality of an element of U, hence is less thanc(U).
By invoking the axiom of foundation, that no set is contained in itself, it can
be shown that c(U)
equals |U|; when the axiom of foundation is not assumed, there are
counterexamples (we may take for example U to be the set of all finite sets of
finite sets etc. of the sets xα where
the index α is any real number, and xα = {xα} for each α. Then U has the cardinality of the continuum,
but all of its members have finite cardinality and so ;
see Bourbaki's article for more details).
Let κ be a strongly
inaccessible cardinal. Say that a set S is strictly of type κ if for any
sequence sn ∈ ... ∈ s0 ∈ S,
|sn| < κ. (Sitself corresponds to the empty
sequence.) Then the set u(κ) of all sets strictly of type κ is a
Grothendieck universe of cardinality κ. The proof of this fact is long, so for
details, we again refer to Bourbaki's article, listed in the references.
To show that the large
cardinal axiom (C) implies the universe axiom (U), choose a set x. Let x0 = x,
and for each n, let xn+1 = xn be the union
of the elements of xn.
Let y = xn.
By (C), there is a strongly inaccessible cardinal κ such that |y| < κ. Let u(κ)be the universe of the
previous paragraph. x is strictly of type κ, so x ∈ u(κ).
To show that the universe axiom (U) implies the large cardinal axiom (C),
choose a cardinal κ. κ is a set, so it is an element of a Grothendieck universe U. The cardinality of U is strongly inaccessible and strictly
larger than that of κ.
In fact, any Grothendieck
universe is of the form u(κ) for some κ. This gives another form of
the equivalence between Grothendieck universes and strongly inaccessible
cardinals:
For any
Grothendieck universe U, |U|
is either zero, ,
or a strongly inaccessible cardinal. And if κ is zero, ,
or a strongly inaccessible cardinal, then there is a Grothendieck universe
u(κ). Furthermore, u(|U|)=U, and |u(κ)| = κ.
Since the existence of
strongly inaccessible cardinals cannot be proved from the axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel
set theory (ZFC), the
existence of universes other than the empty set and cannot be
proved from ZFC either. However, strongly inaccessible cardinals are on the
lower end of the list of large cardinals;
thus, most set theories that use large cardinals (such as "ZFC plus there is
a measurable cardinal",
"ZFC plus there are infinitely many Woodin cardinals") will prove that
Grothendieck universes exist.
See also[edit]
References[edit]
1.
Jump up^ Streicher, Thomas (2006). "Universe
in a Topos". From
Sets and Types to Topology and Analysis: Towards Practicable Foundations for
Constructive Mathematics.
Clarendon Press. pp. 78––90. ISBN 9780198566519.
Bourbaki,
Nicolas (1972). "Univers". In Michael Artin, Alexandre
Grothendieck, Jean-Louis Verdier,
eds. Séminaire de Géométrie Algébrique du Bois Marie - 1963-64 -
Théorie des topos et cohomologie étale des schémas - (SGA 4) - vol. 1 (Lecture
notes in mathematics 269) (in
French). Berlin; New York: Springer-Verlag. pp. 185–217.
·
This page was last modified on 10
February 2014 at 21:16.
·
Text is available under the Creative
Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License;
additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Useand Privacy
Policy.
Wikipedia® is a registered t
Wikipedia® is a registered t
沒有留言:
張貼留言